Research Articles

Geography’s “World view”: The ontological issues of geography

  • LIU Kai , 1 ,
  • TANG Maolin , 2, * ,
  • LIU Rongzeng 1 ,
  • QIN Yaochen 3
Expand
  • 1. School of Resources and Environment Science, Henan University of Economics and Law, Zhengzhou 450002, China
  • 2. School of Geographical Sciences & Jiangsu Center for Collaborative Innovation in Geographical Information Resource Development and Application, Nanjing Normal University, Nanjing 210023, China;
  • 3. Ministry of Education Key Laboratory of Geospatial Technology for Middle and Lower Yellow River Regions, Henan University, Kaifeng 475001, Henan, China

Author: Liu Kai (1972-), PhD and Associate Professor, specialized in the philosophy of geography, geographical information science, urban and regional development. E-mail:

Received date: 2017-06-03

  Accepted date: 2017-07-17

  Online published: 2017-12-10

Supported by

Humanities and Social Science Research Project of Ministry of Education Fund, No.15YJA720003

Copyright

Journal of Geographical Sciences, All Rights Reserved

Abstract

Contemporary science philosophy suggests that discussing ontological problems is of fundamental significance broadly within certain specific disciplines. Natural and social science research are inseparable from philosophical guidance; for instance, the philosophy of geography is the ideological basis for geography. The traditional philosophy of geography is methodology- oriented, which primarily emphasizes the “logical structure of geography explanations,” and ignores the discussion of its ontology. This study, in the context of the philosophy of science, explores the relationships between methodology, ontology, and the philosophy of geography, defines the connotations of geographical ontology, analyzes the links and differences between philosophical ontology and scientific ontology of geography, clarifies the nature of geographical ontology, and summaries its theoretical values. The ontology of geography incorporates the philosophically ontological beliefs of geographers and geographical schools and the ontological commitment of the theory of geography. As different geographers hold different philosophical viewpoints, their ontological beliefs are different; one geographical theory asserts an ontological commitment of “what is there,” which determines the nature and types of objectives the theory references. The ontological beliefs of geographers determine their epistemology, methodology, and axiology, and the ontological commitment of a geographical theory is the premise and basis of that theory.

Cite this article

LIU Kai , TANG Maolin , LIU Rongzeng , QIN Yaochen . Geography’s “World view”: The ontological issues of geography[J]. Journal of Geographical Sciences, 2017 , 27(12) : 1541 -1555 . DOI: 10.1007/s11442-017-1451-z

1 Introduction

The term ontology originates from ancient Greece. Etymologically, “onto” means “being,” and “logy” (logos in Greek) means “science.” Therefore, ontology is a discipline that researches “being” (Lawson, 2015), and is also a science researching the general nature and law of being (Yu, 2012). Scholars in computing and information have introduced philosophical ontology into their own disciplines and specifically define it as a science that investigates the object type, structure, attributes, process, and relationships within all substantial fields (Smith, 2003). The broad philosophy of science defines the ontology of science as, “‘what exists in the world’ according to the theoretical idea which is widely accepted by the current science” (Worrall, 1994). Philosophers regard ontology as a synonym for metaphysics (Smith, 2003). For example, Heidegger (1996) believes that “all metaphysical thoughts are ontology, or they are nothing.”
Modern research on (social) philosophy of science shows that ontology is an essential theoretical issue in philosophy of science and theoretical research in specific disciplines (Burian and Trout, 1995) and each empirical science requires certain metaphysical foundations (Esfeld, 2006; Dilworth, 1996). With the contemporary renaissance of ontology (Yu, 2002), the ontologies of economics (Mäki, 2001), politics (Stanley, 2012; Chatterjee, 2011), history (Pang, 1988), natural science (scientific realism) (Worrall, 1994), mathematics (Tymoczko, 1991), physics (Harre, 1997) and so on are widely and deeply discussed. These philosophical discussions promote the theoretical development of the relevant disciplines. Compared with the broader ontology, which is the basic research content of the philosophy, discipline-specific ontology reflects the researcher’s basic belief and concept about the research object.
Since the conception of modern geography, geographical nature and methodology have been discussed throughout its development (Liu, 2013). Immanuel Kant examined the knowledge system and nature of geography very early, and proposed the field of geography as “science about space.” It was these philosophical ideas that formed the geographical methodology of the successive geographers Hettner (1983) and Hartshorne (1958) to some extent, and was the beginning of systematic philosophical research into geography. After the 1920s, with the philosophy of science maturing and influencing geography, a dispute between the methodologies of Hartshorne (1958) and Schaefer (1953) appeared, which initiated a quantitative revolution aimed at theorization. After the 1970s, the appearance and development of humanistic geography, radical geography, and post-modern geography diversified philosophical and methodological research in geography. Geographers began to show an interest in the methodological principles of different philosophical schools within geographical research, and comprehensively discuss their philosophical beliefs and the ontology of philosophy (Johnston, 1986). With the wide application of spatial analysis methods to geography, some scholars began to realize that discussions on the ontology of geography had been neglected (Johnston, 2003).
Systematic philosophical research on geography in China dates back to the Philosophy of Geography, written by Bai in the Republic of China (Ma and Fang, 2010). However, while the domestic geography made great achievements after the founding of the People’s Republic of China, philosophical research and high-level theoretical research in geography consistently lagged within academic circles (Cai, 1992; Ye and Cai, 2009). Bai (1995) attributed the source of this neglect to the philosophical poverty of geography. Scholars, such as Cai and Ye, called to strengthen the discussion and innovation of geographical methodology (Tang, 2010; Ye and Cai, 2010) and philosophical and theoretical research in geography (Li, 2003; Ye and Cai, 2010). Some researchers have engaged in discussions of geographical methodology and certain progress has been made (Cai et al., 2011; Tang, 2010). However, philosophical research on geography still generally lags behind as a whole, and examining the ontology of geography is still not taken seriously. The lack of interest is directly related to the historical development of ontology; however, it also reflects the poor development of geographical philosophy in China. Due to the prerequisite status of ontology compared with epistemology and methodology (Liam, 2012), discussing the ontology of geography is of vital significance. The objective of this work is to discuss the definition, connotation, and nature of the ontology of geography and its relationship with methodology from the perspective of the philosophy of science. Furthermore, it summarizes the value and practical significance of research on ontology for the theoretical and philosophical development of geography.

2 Significance of methodology and ontology of geography

Science and philosophy circles hold similar views that scientific research requires philosophical guidance, contemplation, and a certain metaphysical foundation (Fry, 2012). Physicist Max Plank (1989) pointed out that “general philosophical thought of researchers will have certain impacts on their scientific research work from beginning to end.” Philosopher Wittgenstein(1996) emphasized that the basic target of philosophy is to clarify thought logically and define it. Geographers also realize the role of philosophy in geography. For example, Hill (1981) pointed out that “all researches are guided by the philosophical belief, which impacts or initiates the selection of the research topic and method to complete the research with constant evolution. In short, the philosophical issues permeate into all aspects of the geographical research.” Anuqin (1994) hypothesized that the “theory of geography was connected in one way or another with philosophy throughout time and in every country.”
Geographical methodology is always a core content concern in geographical philosophy. Several significant disputes occurred in the history of geography, which facilitated the innovation of geographical thought and enriched geographical philosophy. Different scholars have discussed the significance of geographical methodology in geography from different perspectives. For example, Schaefer (1953) hypothesized that “methodology properly deals with the position and scope of the field within the total system of the sciences and with the character and nature of its concepts,” and Hettner (1927) pointed out that “the scientific research on methodology is more important than scientific definition.” However, varying hypotheses have been proposed for the connotation of methodology. Johnston (1986) proposed that methodology is “a set of rules and procedures indicating how the research and argument go in the discipline,” while Cai et al. (2011) proposed that methodology is the scientization of method.
Geographical research requires both methodology and a complete philosophical framework. Harvey (1971) suggested that “only to select a methodology with logical coherence cannot solve the geographical problems and more things are required. ‘More things’ means appropriate geographical philosophy … If a philosophical decision is not made for certain research target object in advance, it is impossible to make a better methodological decision.” Here, the “philosophical decision” for “certain research target object” implies a definition of a certain ontology. Johnston (1986) hypothesized that “every disciplinary philosophy contains both an epistemology and an ontology… these are used to define a methodology.” Kitchin and Tate (2013) instead defined methodology as, “a set of rules and procedures to investigate and research certain phenomenon or situation (subject to the epistemology and ontology within this framework),” while the ontology is “a series of specific assumptions supporting the theoretical and ideological system.” While discussing the methodology of geographical science, Qian Xuesen required compliance with the logical principle of the unification of general ontology and methodology (Sun et al., 2013).
In short, methodology is one aspect of research on geographical philosophy. Geographical philosophy both investigates methodology and discusses ontology. These actions comply with a logical philosophical relationship and internal requirement for improving and developing geographical philosophy. After the founding of the People’s Republic of China, geographical philosophy in China was discussed within the framework of epistemology and methodology, which trapped some scholars in a misunderstanding of geographical philosophy as epistemology and methodology in a narrow sense; this muddled the relationship between geographical philosophy and epistemology and methodology, needlessly narrowing and discriminating scholar’s understanding of geographical philosophy. Therefore, this may have limited innovation in geographical theory to epistemology and methodology, and neglected the fact that the source of geographical ideological transmutation is a revolution of a geographer’s “world view” and ontology. Therefore, examining the ontology of geography is helpful for scholars to fully understand geographical philosophy, systematically develop it, and provide new dimensions and paths for the theoretical development of geography.

3 Philosophical and logic basis for research on ontology of geography

3.1 The renaissance of ontology and research gaps

Ontology was once the core of traditional western philosophy. Modern western philosophy began with the realization of the opposition of thought and being. Namely, people cannot correctly perceive the ontology of world from the opposition of the subject and object. With the epistemological focus of the modern philosophical research, traditional ontology has gradually faded away. Logical positivism divides the proposition into the empirical proposition and metaphysical proposition, judges the latter with the standard “verified with experience” and hypothesizes that it is impossible to verify or falsify it, which is meaningless, and thus rejects all metaphysical and ontological propositions. From this process, research on ontology declined.
Willard Van Orman Quine revived the issues inherent in ontology (Yang, 2008), and the criticism on “two doctrines” of logical empiricism shifted its theoretical foundation. Quine hypothesized that the basic ontology may be simply summarized to “what is there,” and ontology is necessary to make theoretical statements and establish the knowledge system (Quine, 1953). Martin Heidegger suggested that philosophy must first address the truth of being itself by distinguishing being from beings (Zhang, 2005). Through these proposals, ontology recovers its deserved status. Compared with traditional ontology, pursuing the origin and root, modern ontology emphasizes relativity, subjectivity, and constructiveness. In the era of post-logical positivism of the philosophy of science, “paradigm theory” of Kuhn(1996), “research tradition” of Laudan (1991), “research programme” of Lakatos (1978), and “scientific realistic theory” of Bunge (2001) acknowledge the fundamental and prerequisite role of ontology in scientific theory. Timothy Williamson demonstrated the inevitability of ontology (Liu, 2016). The ontology of Martin Heidegger hypothesizes that scientific practice relies on a transcendental understanding of the physical “being” in this field, which determines the methodology and conceptualization of science (Rouse, 2015). Scholars have discovered that science must be based on certain metaphysics (Plank, 1989; Li, 2008), and scientific explanations requiring ontological commitment has become consensus of most scholars (Wu, 2006).
Traditional geographical philosophy focuses primarily on methodology, or the range of study is generally limited to methodology and epistemology, and thus the issues discussed are often limited to the framework of the “logical structure of the geographical explanation,” or stress the ontology of philosophy (see Johnston, 1986, 2003). This lacks elaboration in the ontology of geography, a common problem in China, with reasons as follows. First, there is a lack of interest in the philosophical research of geography. Second, empiricism (and positivism) has always dominated the geographical research (Tang, 2009). For example, in a comparative analysis of geographical methodologies of the regional school and logical positivism, scholars only select them according to different philosophical standpoints and methodologies for analysis and interpretation. They do not comprehensively discuss the essential differences between ontological ideas in geography that reflect their philosophical standpoints. The last outstanding point is geographical computationalism. When people simulate and forecast the geographical system using computer, cellular automation, multi-agent and related technology, they proceed without examining the application premise, nature, and effects in terms of ontology, which generally reflects the lack of the research on the ontology of geography.
In the geography discipline, ontology has not drawn attention from the public, and research results that reflect on and discuss modern geographical theoretical and philosophical problems from an ontological perspective are rare. However, some geographers have pointed out the lack of published ontological discussions. For example, Johnston (2003) submitted that “epistemology of the spatial analysis is an important issue. However, comparing with the condition that most people apply the statistical methods following the tide of quantitative revolution, almost nobody discusses the epistemology and ontology in detail.” In China, Li et al. (2010) compared classical geography and geographical ontology and methodology from a complex scientific perspective and the ontology of geography has drawn attention from some scholars (Li et al., 2010; Liu, 2013).

3.2 Philosophical and logical basis of research on ontology of geography

Philosophy is a systematic and theoretical worldview and methodology( Karl Marx defined the philosophy as systematized and theorized world view and methodology, and it is widely believed in the domestic philosophical circle that his ontology is the material ontology.) and ontology is, in essence, a worldview (Zhang, 1995; Zhou, 2003). The ontology of philosophy examines universal being, while the ontology of science examines a specific being in a certain field. Therefore, their relationship is between the general and individual, and the ontology of philosophy guides the ontology of science (Sun, 1985). To explore unknown natural or social subjects, science must first presuppose an ontological premise for the external world (Wu, 2006). When researching the object and content of specific science, the specific content, range, type, mode of existence, and nature of the research object and their mutual relationships are presupposed and researchers’ ontology is established. For example, when researching the geographical issue of “peasant household” in geography, the concept “peasant household” acknowledges its existence. Subsequently, the nature and type are assumed, which are the specific geographical ontological presuppositions.
Modern science philosophers have proposed theories that incorporate ontology. For example, the “paradigm shift” proposed by Thomas S. Kuhn mainly consists of three parts, namely, ontology, methodology, and axiology; the root cause lies in the fundamental change of the world view and ontology of the scientific community (Laudan, 1984); the “research tradition” proposed by Laudan (1991) consists of ontology and methodology (Meng, 1989), “in short, a research tradition is ‘what to do’ and ‘what not to do’ of a set of ontology and methodology.” Hanson’s (1958) “theory-laden observations” also point out that the observation depends on theory, and the theoretical basis and determination of the observation object and range are the observer’s ontological presupposition (Lund et al., 2011). In geographical research circles, Harvey (1996) hypothesized that the worldview and philosophical belief are decisive for geographical research, “the key point of our current purpose is to indicate that such philosophy depends on the belief … However, we cannot make analysis without its foundation … Therefore, the philosophical belief or geographical nature is decisive for engaging in the material geographical work.” Anuqin (1994) hypothesized that “the theoretical concepts of geographers mirrored the views of certain philosophers.” Furthermore, Johnston (2000) proposed that the “use of the methodology allows the accumulation of a disciplinary store of knowledge, the resu1ts of work aimed at comprehending a particular topic and which are accepted as valid because they were collected within the criteria of epistemology and ontology that are part of the relevant philosophy.”
The paradigm of any natural and social science has consistent principles and stands at the ontological level. These fundamental and transcendental ontological presuppositions for “what is there” in a specific field fundamentally restricts and defines the selection of the corresponding methodology and paradigm. Furthermore, they provide a framework for researching relevant specific issues. Ontology constitutes the key components of metaphysics. Generally speaking, metaphysics is different from a specific science that solves correspondingly unique problems, and advocates releasing limitations from individual experiences and examines problems with a long-term perception. In modern scientific research, philosophical and scientific research influence each other. With further expansion of the research field and requirements for theoretical development, a reasonable ontological solution becomes a basic premise to solve other problems. Similar to other sciences and social science, geographical research is conducted under the guidance of a certain philosophical framework, in which the ontology is the prerequisite and fundamental status. The ontology of geography is its “world view,” which presupposes both existence and a mode of existence, which is the metaphysical foundation of geography.
It is recognized within scientific philosophy and geographical research circles that ontology and worldview are basic factors in scientific research. Geography explores the unknown geographical world and the basic concept of geographers for “what exists” in this geographical world reflects the ontological presupposition of the external geographical world. Without clarification of this basic premise, the selection of any geographical research and methodology will exhibit blind behavior without basis and logical premise. Metaphysical interpretations and analyses are very common in geographical research. Philosophers, geographers, and geographical scholars often use various metaphysical facts when criticizing, evaluating, supporting, and interpreting the geographical practice. With the ontological prerequisite for methodology and entire philosophical framework, geography urgently requires ontological examination and reflection compared with methodological innovation.

4 Connotation and nature of ontology of geography

4.1 Two levels of connotation for the ontology of geography

Philosophical ontology is the “theory and research of the basic nature of all realities” (Yu, 2012). The philosophy of science internalizes the research on “what the object world is” for certain disciplines, i.e., “what is its nature.” According to Quine (1953), basic ontological issue may be summarized into a question of “what is there?” and its nature. Therefore, the ontology of geography addresses “what is there in the geographical world?” Different answers to this question reflect the different ontological beliefs of geographers and geographical theories. For example, geographers (such as Ratzel) that favor social biological ontology (social Darwinism) hypothesize that “a state is a biological organism,” which is similar to an organism or biological organic organization form, and whose behaviors comply with biological rules. Geographers favoring ontology of mechanism hypothesize that “the geographical world is a machine” and relationships between objects in the geographical world are mechanically deterministic. Geographers favoring computationalism ontology hypothesize that the “geographical world is a computer” and regard the geographical system as a cellular automaton.
For geographers, the ontology of geography is reflected in their basic beliefs regarding the geographical world, and their basic definition of the geographical being when geography is researched. This presupposes the object, range, content, nature, and characteristics of the geographical world. For example, what are the elements of the geographical world? Are they material or spiritual? What geographical entities do they include? How they are combined? Which kind of principles control their functions and change? What is the nature of the geographical causal relationship? Is the determinism of geographical environment correct? What is the relationship between geographical elements? How has the geographical world evolved and developed? The ontology of geography first reflects the worldview of geographers, i.e., their general opinions and concepts, which may be called the geographical world of geographers. That is, the geographical world is a part of the world, which has its own range and is distinguished from other worlds. The history of geographical thought tells us that the range and content of the geographical world for different geographers are uncertain, are continuously changing as the discipline develops.
What kinds of other biological, physical, and social beings are presupposed as beings of the geographical world? What kind of dependent relationships exist between geographical phenomena in the geographical world, i.e., deterministic, indeterministic, simple linear or complex non-linear? The existence of a strict geographical law in the geographical world is also an important ontological question. Is the geographical object the “location” (Bunge, 1991), “landscape” (Williams, 1989), “regional difference” (Hartshorne, 1959) or “areal system of man-earth relationship”? It is an ontological presupposition and implies certain transcendental statements of an object’s nature. The content, range, and nature of the geographical object are determined by the ontological commitment held by the geographer. The set of such ontological commitments has a systematic worldview nature, which determines how the content relating to geography from this world is selected. Furthermore, this worldview defines the basic characteristics and nature of the geographical being and its relationships. Such ontological commitments of geographers have a fundamental role, more fundamental than other factors in the belief system. Moreover, once they are obtained, it is difficult to correct them. Meanwhile, they are obtained through presupposition, rather than inference. When a geographer faces a specific problem, such philosophical belief is converted into the presupposition of the specific geographical problem, namely “what the research object involved is (what exists).” In addition, according to Quine’s ontological argument, theoretically, “The question of the ontological commitments of a theory , then, is the question what, according to that theory, there is.” (Quine, 1966). Therefore, the ontology of geography is “about what the object of certain geographical theory is or which kind of geographical things exist according to certain geographical theory?”
Therefore, the connotation of the ontology of geography shall include at least two aspects. The first is the philosophical ontological belief of a geographer or geographical school. The ontology of philosophy researches the overall being, which masters their nature and law. Different geographers and geographical schools have different worldview and ontological beliefs. The second aspect is the ontological presupposition of a geographical theory. Namely, what kind of geographical beings does this theory presuppose (which kind of realities)? What is their nature? What is the relationship between elements? How they are evolved and developed? The former is the philosophical ontology of geography and the latter is the scientific ontology of geography. Moreover, the philosophical ontology is traditionally regarded as taking precedence over the scientific ontology in terms of logic and epistemology (Zhang, 2000). Based on the basic perspective of philosophical ontology, the scientific ontology of geography is the basic assumption of geographical theory.
The philosophical ontology of geography reflects the basic concept and philosophical standpoint of the geographer and geographical school for the being. For example, the ontology of empiricism is that “the things that we experience are the things that exist,” the ontology of humanism is that “what exists is that which people perceive to exist” (Johnston, 1986). Given that spirit is the source of the world, the ontology of idealism is that “to be means to be perceived.” In contrast, given materials as the source of the world, the ontology of materialism is that spirit is the “objective reflection of the material.” The ontological presupposition of geographical theory is its premise, namely, what geographical beings (realities) are presupposed by this theory? What is their nature? What is the relationship between geographical elements? How do they evolve and develop? The core conceptual structure of this theory is reflected in form.
The first aspect may be summarized into a general form: “what are the ontological and worldview beliefs of a geographical school or geographer?” or “what ontological belief does the ‘humanistic geography’ have?” The latter may be summarized into, “what does the geographical theory T presuppose for P?” Specifically, for example, the “classical agricultural location theory” in economic geography presupposes that the freight of a single factor determines the location of agricultural land utilization and its core conceptual structure is “agricultural location, the single factor of distance, determinism, and isolated state, as well consistent conditions.” In comparison, the “modern agricultural location theory” presupposes that factors, such as technology, nature, society, economy, and behavior, determine the agricultural location and its core conceptual structure is “agricultural location decision, ‘natural, social, economic, technical and behavioral multi-factor’, incomplete determinism, and regional difference.” When specific geographical problems are solved, the ontology at both of these levels will be fully reflected.

4.2 Diversification, relativity and openness of the ontology of geography

Varying ontological choices for different geographers reflect their different worldview beliefs about the geographical world and their ontological premise when researching specific geographical problems and theory. Specifically, these choices will include the kind of entity and object geographers presuppose for specific fields or problems - their nature, structure, process, and relation - and the theory and model basis employed for problem analysis, which are the logical research starting point for a geographer. Different geographers and geographical schools philosophically hold different ontological concepts. Moreover, they hold different ontological commitments at the level of geographical theory, reflecting their diversity.
When specific geographical problems are faced and solved, different answers to the ontological question of “what exists” reflect the use of different theoretical frameworks, conceptual systems, cognition paths, and selection of different methods and procedures. For this problem, Johnston (1986) advocated that, “science is the pursuit of systematic and formulated knowledge, and as such is not confined to any particular epistemology.” For example, the philosophical foundation of positivist geography is logical positivism, which rejects the ontological issue, or in other words, it is committed to “only things which may be directly observed are acceptable evidence” (Johnston, 1986). It hypothesizes that the existence of certain geographical phenomenon entails the existence of certain experiences, which require evidence to certify their existence; logical positivist is the realist of certain experiences. Humanistic geography is philosophically based on phenomenology, which requires that the phenomenon is the starting point of all ontologies, “appearance” is “reality,” the subject and object are unified in phenomenon perception, and people perceive the existence of certain geographical phenomena.
With the development of science and practice, society’s view of the world has also changed. Ontology has also gone through modern “spiritual ontology” (such as Hegel) and “material ontology” (such as Marx), rejection of ontology by the modern logical positivism, rebuilding of ontology by Quine and colleagues, phenomenological ontology with “phenomenon” and “reality” unified from the ancient “primordial ontology”. Ontology was finally followed by the development of negation of negation (Zhang, 2000). The history of ontology shows that ontology is relative, open, and developing. Therefore, the ontology of geographers shall also be relative, open, and developing. In the history of geographical thought, different viewpoints of the human-earth relationship, geographical worldview, and nature of geographical objects are the primary expressions of ontological difference. The gradual development process of geographers’ cognition of the ontology of geography is reflected in the following changes: from a “simple and rigid” geographical worldview to the “complex and systematic” geographical worldview, from the ontological presupposition of “mechanical determinism” of the “determinism of geographical environment” to “dialectical determinism” of “probabilism” and ontological commitment of “harmony theory”, from the ontological separation of “nature” and “economy” to unified geography.

4.3 Prerequisites, fundamentality, and limitation of the ontology of geography

Philosophically, ontology is a basic constitution of philosophy. If ontology were the root of a big tree, then philosophy, epistemology, axiology, and other philosophical ramifications may be regarded as branches of this tree (Liu, 1996). Ontology determines the epistemology, and is its presupposition, and limits and guides its direction and mode. The direction and path difference of epistemology are the mark and inclination of ontological difference (Zhang, 1995). As methodology and ontology are unified, the method is a medium to reach reality. Methodology is the ways to solve problems based on a particular worldview or in agreement with ontological principles. Therefore, ontology determines the answers to methodological and epistemological questions, determining the selection of the research method (Cuba and Lincoln, 1994).
Any scientific theory and thought require certain ontological foundation, namely, basis, principle, and logical starting point constituting this theory and thought. As Quine (1961) said, “One’s ontology is basic to the conceptual scheme by which he interprets all experiences, even the most commonplace ones,” “Our ontology is determined once we have fixed upon the over-all conceptual scheme which is to accommodate science in the broadest sense.” More specifically, all scientists’ theories hold particular ontological standpoints and imply a denial or acknowledgement that the ontological presupposition “something exists.” As Peet (2007) argued, “the so-called theory means a narrative system, which has epistemological judgment, ontological definition, and special experience demonstration, establishes a definite conceptual range and expresses a set of consistent viewpoint content.” Each independent science has its own special research object and understanding and defining it are basic ontological issues, which determine the basic worldview and standardize the category of the research object. Therefore, the specific building of the ontology of geography determines the starting point of the corresponding geographical theory, corresponding methodology, logical structure, and theoretical form. For geographers, ontology is the main content of their worldview, which is also basic judgment and presupposition of the geographical research object, and plays a fundamental guiding role with its internal uniformity with methodology.
Geographers have proposed various theories that may be partially interpreted as fact because of an ontological commitment. The reasonable answer to the question of the ontology of geography is a premise and decisive factor for the theoretical development of geography. In answering geographical questions, if the idea of philosophical ontology, basic theory and model presupposition, range, reality, attribute, process, and relationships of research objects and other ontological questions are deviated from or do not comply with the geographical fact, the conclusion will be unreliable no matter the type of method employed. This is the fundamental and prerequisite role of ontology. Geographical thought, interpretation, theory, and methodology contain certain ontological assumptions. Moreover, the epistemology and methodology cannot be philosophically and logically separated from the ontological presupposition. There are no epistemologies or methodologies with neutral ontologies, which reflect the limitation of ontology.

5 Theoretical value of the ontology of geography

For geographical interpretation, theoretical development, and solving of specific problems, the value of ontology lies in answering the following questions: What is the philosophical ontology of certain geographical thought? What are the ontological presuppositions of certain geographical theory? How are such presuppositions limited and determined from geographical worldview beliefs of geographers? Are these presuppositions reasonable? How can we verify and judge them? Do certain geographical phenomena exist? Answers to these questions are the basic starting point for theoretical and practical applied research in geography, which reflect the basic ideas of the research object of the geographers or researchers. Their fundamental value lies in establishing an ultimate basis for solving geographical problems; therefore, our selection of epistemology and method is made on a reliable and reasonable basis. During practice, the realization of the theoretical value of ontology of geography is reflected in the ontological analysis, introspection, and criticism.

5.1 Analysis of the ontology of geography

During geographical research, ontology is the basic idea and presupposition of geographers regarding a research object. To interpret the objective geographical world, geographers must definitely or implicitly presuppose an ontology answer to the fundamental question “what exists in the geographical world?” Such presupposition is very common and necessary for geographers. For certain geographical theory and thought, the ontology is the premise and foundation to make a point. Without such presupposition, it is impossible to perform basic theoretical analysis and logical reasoning. Therefore, to analyze a basic idea in geographical theory and school, ontological analysis is a very useful method. With such analysis, we may essentially master the basic idea, presupposition, and ideological connotation of the geographical theory and relevant school thought. Furthermore, we may reveal its reasonable and unreasonable points and space, approach, and measures for theoretical improvement. Geographical interpretation must be based on the premise of basic presuppositions of the geographical reality for geographers. Analysis of this premise may help us select reasonable geographical theories for interpretation and analysis, making the theoretical and interpretative ontological premise consistent. For specific problems, the value of analyzing geographical ontology lies in determining the boundary for specific geographical problems and providing a basis for the geographical theory and model employed. The objective geographical world is changing and developing, which requires us to analyze the ontological characteristics of the research object when researching geographical issues. We must require that the theoretical presupposition and analysis premise comply with the objective reality, resulting in more scientific and reasonable assumptions and interpretations. The basic ontological analysis methods include language analysis, conceptual analysis, and historical analysis.

5.2 Introspection on the ontology of geography

When geographers contemplate and implement geographical research, introspection on ontology is the ontological examination, introspection, and reflection for the geographical thought, theory, model, and method employed. Generally, this self-selection is made based on geographical fact assumptions and the main components of their basic academic accomplishments. Geographers’ philosophical ontological beliefs, scientific ontological commitments of geography, and ontological presupposition of geographical problems are very important, and directly impact their interpretation results. Negligence of the ontological issue of geography and emphasizing the significance of methodology results in insufficient concern and contemplation for the ontological presuppositions made to research and interpret geographical issues. Certain deviations from basic premise definitions of the specific geographical problem, judgments on the practical nature and relationships of the geographical object not complying with the objective world, or theory and model employed not complying with the actual situation can all result from neglecting ontology.
The ontological introspection on geography also includes the ontology of philosophy and science. Introspection on the ontology of philosophy reflects the introspection of the philosophical standpoint that we employ. In comparison, introspection on the ontology of science reflects the theory, model, and problem presupposition employed. For example, is our philosophical standpoint idealistic or materialistic? Is it mechanical deterministic or is a complicated system worldview employed? These questions belong to the former introspection on philosophy. Do certain geographical phenomena exist? Is it appropriate to use this model? Is the theory used suitable for the specific geographical phenomenon? These questions belong to the latter introspection on science. The assumptions have a certain ontology status, which is a basic judgment on geographical things. Such judgment impacts the basic analysis result. The essence of the geographical model is that it has theoretical ontological status, which summarizes the essential relationship between geographical things. Changing the geographical phenomenon and reality, or the nature and relationships, i.e., the corresponding objective reality is changed, the judgment of the basic nature and relationships of geographical things does not comply with objective facts, or the theoretical ontological assumption is used by adhering to a previous assumption, it is impossible to perform a reasonable analysis that complies with objective fact. This is a typical error from ontological presuppositions.

5.3 Criticism in the ontology of geography

In the philosophical context, the meaning of criticism has been impacted by Immanuel Kant. Criticism is generally defined as the reflective inspection of the effectiveness and limitation of the human’s capacity or a series of philosophical propositions. In philosophy, the ontological criticism is often the reflective inspection of the ontological rationality premise for other philosophical thought foundations, which is the speculative application of critical thinking. With reference to the meaning of philosophical criticism, the ontological criticism of geography is a systematic examination, which is an overall review of the thought foundation and theoretical basis for certain convictions. Criticism, in this context, is designed to understand the effectiveness, limitations, and applicability of geography.
The ontological criticism of geography is the main approach to reflectively understand and tentatively apply various geographical thoughts, basic concepts, and various theoretical premises and assumptions. There has always been a relatively lack of critical courage, spirit, and practice in geographical academic circles in China, which causes a lack of critical thinking given to domestic research on geographical thought and theory, and insufficient dialogue (Tang, 2010). This situation is unfavorable for further development of theory and thought. Constructive criticism of theory and thought requires ontological criticism, which is favorable for the healthy development of academic controversy and creation of healthy academic environment for academic innovation, which will lead to the development and advancement of new ideas and theories.

6 Conclusions

Geographical philosophy is the philosophical reflection and summary of geography. Similar to other natural and social sciences, philosophical research in geography incorporates ontological issues. The ontology of geography is its “worldview,” which presupposes existence in the geographical world, mode of existence, and mutual interaction. Proposing and examining ontological issues in geography is important for philosophical and theoretical research. The development of geographical theory and practice, and innovation in geographical methodology are impossible without innovation in philosophical thought and breakthrough in ontological and epistemological frameworks. The prerequisite and fundamental status of ontological issues for geographical philosophy and theory and specific geographical problem suggests certain requirements. We should adopt ontologically cautious attitudes for addressing specific geographical problems, have receptive and experimental temperaments when engaging in geographical theory, and provide critical and opening perspectives for philosophical problems.
Innovation in contemporary geographical theory, concepts, and methodology also requires systematic thinking and reflection from the perspective of ontology. Developments in geographical philosophy are the source and the driving force of theoretical development and advancing the geography disciplines. Geographical philosophy has remained a weak link in fundamental geographical research. In contemporary geography, investigating philosophical problems in geography from an ontological perspective provides both systematic observations and new avenues of exploration. This is helpful for establishing the correct ontological premise and methodological innovation when researching specific geographical problems, enriching philosophical concepts in geography, and enhancing the philosophical consciousness of geographical research.

The authors have declared that no competing interests exist.

[1]
Anuqin B A, 1994. The Theoretical Problems of Geography. Beijing: The Commercial Press, 83-84. (in Chinese)

[2]
Bai G, 1995. The philosophical predicament in the development of geography.Acta Geographica Sinica, 50(3): 279-287. (in Chinese)Immannel kant raised that space can exist without material, thus human knowledge can be classified into history, geography and other sciences corresponding to space and time in phiosophy. Geography is a subject which researches the relations among different things but the universal character.In fact. time and space are both exist in the moving matter, space-time can not be separated frommaterial. The Kantian thought leads to the centrifugation and dispersion in geography and the scientific cognition system can not be set up for geography.Neo-kantiansm considers natural science as the subject to establish regulation and social science as the subject to record and narrate individuality. They have great difference in methodology.This thought is the philosophical basis of dualism in geography. It causes that geography is divided into physical geography and human geography over a long time. The regional school whose representative figures are Alfred Hettner and Richarel Hartshorne. regards geography as the science to narrate individuality. It leads geography to deviate from universal scientific methodology, and take the road of isolationism and execptism. It hinders the development of geography.Logical Positivism advocates unity in scientific methodology. It is of positive significance to the development of geography. But it considers geography as a space science, in this extent, return to the kantianism that ignores the research on the surface material environment. " quantitative revolution" and " theoretical revolution" in geography do not make remarkable achievement because the revolutions are influenced by the above methodology and the methodology for simple system is applied to study the complicated system.In 1960's, with the outstanding environmental problems, social needs are raising for geography.At the same time. the improvement of methodology on complicated system provides favorable conditions for geography development.Although advanced technological means is very important in the development of geography, the key to the question is to have a correct epistemology and methodology. On the development of modern geography, we have some philosophical thought as the follows.To hold firmly to monism in geography. It does not mean that subjects should be mixed and systematic geography should be negated. It means regarding epigeosphere system as a developing evolution integration. Geography environment is a unitary connective integration which is made up of man and nature. Geography dualism to research on pure nature or pure society is wrong. The view of mechanism that wants to distinguish the proportion of nature or society from the whole system is wrong either, but research from the viewpoint of integrated law is the right way. Geographic environment is a unity composed of time-space and moving matter. The view that only researches on the space from the material environment separates the objective world. Geography study must return to the epigeosphere.Toattach importance to the study of the global environment. This is the basic point of theoratical study in geography just as the significance or atom and molecule in chemistry and physics. Global system is the basic point of geography study. The planetary law and the law of matter cycle and energy transformation on earth surface control and influence the motion and evolution of every part or factor of the epigeosphere.To strengthen the study of classification. Though there is difference in thousands of ways on the epigeosphere it can be differentiated as regional types and environmental types. Exploring the general law of the same type has universal significance for recognizing and building environment and benefits to the construction of geographical theory.To strengthen the study of modelling. It is difficult to find out closed " geographical generally acknowledged" or " geographical law" because of the complicaton and variety of geographical environment. Modelling approaches the practical fact more than rule. Model is the junior general knowldge and is a bridge to theory.

[3]
Bunge M, 2001. Scientific Realism: Selected Essays of Mario Bunge. Martin M ed. New York:Prometheus Books.Machine generated contents note: I. METAPHYSICS -- 1. How Do Realism , Materialism, and Dialectics Fare in Contemporary Science? (1973) -- 2. New Dialogues between Hylas and Philonous (1954) -- 3. Energy: Between Physics and Metaphysics (2000) -- 4. The Revival of Causality (1982) -- 5. Emergence and the Mind (1977) -- 6 SCIENTIFIC REALISM -- 6. The Status of Concepts (1981) -- 7. Popper's Unworldly World 3 (1981) --II. METHODOLOGY AND PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE -- 8. On Method in the Philosophy of Science (1973) -- 9. Induction in Science (1963) -- 10. The GST Challenge to the Classical Philosophies of Science (1977) -- 11. The Power and Limits of Reduction (1991) -- 12. Thinking in Metaphors (1999) --III. PHILOSOPHY OF MATHEMATICS -- 13. Moderate Mathematical Fictionism (1997) -- 14. The Gap between Mathematics and Reality (1994) -- 15. Two Faces and Three Masks of Probability (1988) --IV. PHILOSOPHY OF PHYSICS -- 16. Physical Relativity and Philosophy (1979) -- 17. Hidden Variables, Separability, and Realism (1995) -- 18. Schrodinger's Cat Is Dead (1999) --V. PHILOSOPHY OF PSYCHOLOGY -- 19. From Mindless Neuroscience and Brainless Psychology to Neuropsychology (1985) -- 20. Explaining Creativity (1993) -- VI. PHILOSOPHY OF SOCIAL SCIENCE -- 21. Analytic Philosophy of Society and Social Science: -- The Systemic Approach as an Alternative to Holism and Individualism (1988) -- 22. Rational Choice Theory: A Critical Look at Its Foundations (1995) -- 23. Realism and Antirealism in Social Science (1993) --VII. PHILOSOPHY OF TECHNOLOGY -- 24. The Nature of Applied Science and Technology (1988) -- 25. The Technology-Science-Philosophy Triangle in Its Social Context (1999) -- 26. The Technologies in Philosophy (1999) --VIII. MORAL PHILOSOPHY -- 27. A New Look at Moral Realism (1993) -- 28. Rights Imply Duties (1999) --IX. SOCIAL AND POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY -- 29. Morality Is the Basis of Legal and Political Legitimacy (1992) -- 30. Technoholodemocracy: An Alternative to -- Capitalism and Socialism (1994) -- Bibliography -- Index of Names -- Index of Subjects.

[4]
Bunge W, 1991. Theoretical Geography. Sweden: The Royal University of Lund, 231-232.

[5]
Burian R M, Trout J D, 1995. Ontological progress in science.Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 25(2): 1-17.Abstract A note of urgency can sometimes be heard, even in otherwise unhurried writers, when they ask for a justification of morality. Unless the ethical life, or (more narrowly) morality, can be justified by philosophy, we shall be open to relativism, amoralism, and disorder. As they often put it: when an amoralist calls ethical considerations in doubt, and suggests that there is no reason to follow the requirements of morality, what can we say to him?.

DOI

[6]
Cai Y, 1992. Preliminary views on some problems in the study philosophy of geography.Human Geography, 7(4): 1-5. (in Chinese)Science is closely related with philosophy. Every discipline should have its own scientific logic, methodology and philosophy. Geography is no exeption. Geographical science is made up of foundational theory applied theory and technology. Above these, there is a higher level of knowledgy, that is geographical philosophy. Geographical philosophy study has specific significance in the develop- ment process of geography. It may promote the integration of all branches in geographical science. The western geographical philosophy has experienced several stages, i.e. experientialism, positivism, humanism and structuralism. Now a pluralistic situa- tion is formed. The summarization of various geographical philosophies and metho- dologies is an important theme, and many relevant monographs have been pub- lished. In China, the study of geographical philosophy is very weak. There are some historical reasons for this condition. A major factor is that there is no geographical philosophy cause in university. Geographical philosophy study is urgent to be proceeded and developed in China. In order to do this, some approaches are suggested in this article.

[7]
Cai Y, Ye C, Chen Y et al., 2011. Methodology of Geography. Beijing: Science Press. (in Chinese)

[8]
Chatterjee A, 2011. Ontology, epistemology and multimethod research in political science.Philosophy of the Social Sciences, 43(1): 73-99.Epistemologies and research methods are not free of metaphysics. This is to say that they are both, supported by (or presumed by), and support (or presume) fundamental ontologies. A discussion of the epistemological foundations of "multimethod" research in the social sciences-in as much as such research claims to unearth "causal" relations-therefore cannot avoid the ontological presuppositions or implications of such a discussion. But though there isn't necessarily a perfect correspondence between ontology, epistemology, and methodology, they do constrain each other. As such it is possible to make methodological choices that are at odds with one's (implicit) ontology or argue from an ontology that is inconsistent one's choice of methods. Yet lack of recognition of this fact has hampered methodological discussions in political science, especially with respect to the discussion on the merits of multimethod research. The ontology implicitly accepted in such discussions is "reductionist" and "regularist," that is, one that respectively defines causes in terms of noncausal relations and states of affair and affirms that such noncausal relations are regularities in nature. This article will argue that any attempt to fit "multimethod" research (where "multimethod" signifies some combination of inferential statistics and case studies) within this narrow ontology is destined to fail since such a metaphysics logically cannot accord case studies a necessary or sufficient role in the in the establishment of causal relations. However, there are metaphysical positions within the ambit of an empiricist philosophy of science that can accommodate multiple methods without contradiction. The article discusses two such ontologies and suggests ways in which they might allow the establishment of a coherent epistemological foundation for multimethod research, however, within a decidedly empiricist philosophy of science.

DOI

[9]
Cuba E G, Lincoln Y S, 1994. Competing paradigms in qualitative research. In: Handbook of Qualitative Research. Thousand Oaks: Sage Publications, 105-117.

[10]
Dilworth C, 1996. The Metaphysics of Science. London: Kluwer Academic.

[11]
Esfeld M, 2006. The impact of science on metaphysics and its limits.Abstracta, 2(2): 86-101.The paper argues for three theses: (1) Metaphysics depends on science as a source of knowledge. Our current scientific theories commit us to certain metaphysical claims. (2) As far as science is concerned, it is sufficient to spell these claims out in such a way that they amount to a parsimonious ontology. That ontology, however, creates a gap between our experience and the scientific view of the world. (3) In order to avoid that gap and to achieve a complete and coherent view of the world including ourselves, we have to enrich that ontology at its foundations, thus making it less parsimonious. The criterion of the integration into a complete and coherent view of the world including ourselves is the way in which the interpretation of scientific theories depends on metaphysics. These three theses are argued for and illustrated by means of two examples from the philosophy of time (eternalism vs. presentism) and the philosophy of mind (mental causation).

[12]
Fry I, 2012. Is science metaphysically neutral?Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 43(3): 665-673.This paper challenges the claim that science is metaphysically neutral upheld by contenders of the separation of peacefully co-existent science and religion and by evolutionary theists. True, naturalistic metaphysical claims can neither be refuted nor proved and are thus distinct from empirical hypotheses. However, metaphysical assumptions not only regulate the theoretical and empirical study of nature, but are increasingly supported by the growing empirical body of science. This historically evolving interaction has contributed to the development of a naturalistic worldview that renounces the necessity of a transcendent god and of purposeful design. The thesis presented here differs not only from the claims of the “separatists” and of evolutionary theists. In pointing to the metaphysical aspects of science, I also criticize the failure of some evolutionary naturalists to distinguish between empirical and metaphysical contentions. Most important, based on the examination of science suggested here, creationists’ false accusation that science is only a naturalistic dogma is refuted. Finally, the difficulties involved in the position endorsed here for the public support of evolution are acknowledged, taking into account the high religious profile of the American society and the social and political context in the US and in other countries.

DOI PMID

[13]
Hanson N R, 1958. Patterns of Discovery: An Inquiry into the Conceptual Foundations of Science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

[14]
Harre R, 1997. Is there a basic ontology for the physical sciences?Dialectica: International Journal of Philosophy, 51(1): 17-34.Recent debates about the values and virtues of the sciences have been marked by philosophical errors and misunderstandings among both the supporters and the critics of the value of science. Some authors, such as Wilson defending the ultimate value of science and Appleyard decrying the influence of scientific modes of thinking, both assume the positivistic stance to understanding science.... [Show full abstract]

DOI

[15]
Hartshone R, 1958. The concept of geography as a science of space, from Kant and Humboldt to Hettner.Annals of the Association of American Geographers, 48(2): 97-108.ABSTRACT We consider a reversible jump process on d whose jump rates themselves are random. We show mean square convergence of this process under diffusion scaling to a limiting Brownian motion with a certain diffusion matrix, characterizing effective conductivity.

DOI

[16]
Hartshorne R, 1959. Perspective on the Nature of Geography. Chicago: Rand McNally & Company, 6-7.

[17]
Harvey D, 1996. Explanation in Geography. Beijing: The Commercial Press. (in Chinese)

[18]
Heidegger M 1996 M 1996. The Selected Works of Heidegger. Shanghai: Joint Publishing Company, 764-765. (in Chinese)

[19]
Hettner A, 1927. Die geographie: Ihre geschichte ihe wesen und ihre methoden. Breslau: Ferdinand HIRT, 131-132.

[20]
Hill M R, 1981. Positivism: A ‘hidden’ philosophy in geography. In: Themes in Geographic Thought. London: Croom Helm, 38-60.

[21]
Johnston R J, 1986. Philosophy and Human Geography. Baltimore: Edward Arnold.

[22]
Johnston R J, 2003. Order in space: Geography as a discipline in distance. In: A Century of British Geography. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 303-345.

[23]
Kitchin R, Tate N J, 2000. Conducting Research into Human Geography: Theory, Methodology and Practice. London: Pearson Education, 7-8.

[24]
Kuhn S T, 1996. The Structure of Scientific Revolution. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

[25]
Lakatos I, 1978. The Methodology of Scientific Research Programmes. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

[26]
Laudan L, 1984. Science and Values. Berkeley: University of California Press, 68-69.

[27]
Laudan L, 1991. Progress and Its Problem. Shanghai: Shanghai Translation Publishing House, 80-81. (in Chinese)

[28]
Lawson T, 2015. A conception of ontology. In: Social Ontology and Modern Economics. London: Routledge, 19-52.

[29]
Li J, 2003. Geography call for new theory.Geography Teaching Reference of Middle School, 25(4): 5-6. (in Chinese)

[30]
Li S, Wang Y, Cai Y, 2010. The paradigm transformation of geography from the perspective of complexity sciences.Acta Geographica Sinica, 65(12): 1315-1324. (in Chinese)Geographic System is fundamentally a complex system with properties(e.g.emergence,nonlinearity,feedbacks,self organization,path dependence,adaptation,and multiple scales) that cannot be explained through understanding the components parts individually.Complexity sciences,rising in the 1980s,has brought a new perspective for the paradigm transformation of geography.This paper briefly reviews the development of complexity sciences and the changing paradigm of geography.Then the performance,characteristics,and causes of complexity in geographic system are explained and analyzed thoroughly.Paradigms,including ontology,epistemology and methodology between classical geography and geography from the perspective of complexity sciences are compared.Six methods(i.e.soft computing,simulating,scaling,Geographic Information System,metaphor and meta-synthetic method) are summarized for the study of complexity in geographic system.In the end,the authors conclude that the paradigm transformation of geography from the perspective of complexity sciences lies in the formation of a new and innovative thinking,which is considered a beyond reductionism,holistic and pattern/process based generalized evolutionary thinking.

DOI

[31]
Li X, 2008. The metaphysical foundation of science: Science presuppositions.Academics in China, 23(2): 15-34. (in Chinese)

[32]
Liu J, 1996. Philosophy and ontology.Journal of Beijing Normal University (Social Science Edition), 57(6): 11-19. (in Chinese)

[33]
Liu J, 2016. On Williamson’s necessitism.Studies in Dialectics of Nature, 32(2): 19-23. (in Chinese)

[34]
Liu K, 2013. On the issues of ontology of geography.Studies in Dialectics of Nature, 29(10): 111-117. (in Chinese)

[35]
Lund M, Chang H, 2011. N R Hanson: observation, discovery, and scientific change. ISIS, 102(3): 593-595.

DOI

[36]
Ma L, Fang X, 2010. Bai Meichu’s ideas on geography expressed in his geographical philosophy. Studies in the History of Natural Sciences, 29(2): 177-184. (in Chinese)Bai Meichu was a famous geographer in China.Geographical Philosophy published in 1923 was one of his representative works.In this book,he claimed that geography belongs to natural science which could be applied to the field of humanities and social sciences.In his view,geography is characterized by being macroscopical,changeable from time to time and from place to place,and temporarily effective for a given period of time and having a strong educational function.He advocated doing geography studies from the perspective of man-environment relationship.Many of the ideas in Geographical Philosophy have strong practical significance.

[37]
Mäki U, 2001. The Economic World View: Studies in the Ontology of Economics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

[38]
Meng J, 1989. On the theory of value of science of Larry Laudan.Studies in Dialectics of Nature, 5(3): 18-25. (in Chinese)

[39]
Pang Z, 1988. The ontology, epistemology and methodology of history.Historical Research, 28(1): 3-13. (in Chinese)

[40]
Peet R, 2007. Modern Geographical Thought. Beijing: The Commercial Press, 17-18. (in Chinese)

[41]
Plank M, 1989. Physics and philosophy.The Philosophical Problems of Natural Science, 8(2): 68-69. (in Chinese)

[42]
Quine W V, 1953. From a Logical Point of View. Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press.

[43]
Quine W V, 1966. The Ways of Paradox and Other Essays. New York: Random House, 127-128.This article has no associated abstract. ()

[44]
Rouse J, 2015. Scientific law, natural necessity, and Heideggerian ontology.Journal of Dialectics of Nature, 37(5): 103-115. (in Chinese)Martin Heidegger's "existential" conception of science and his account of the ontological difference between being and entities develop a novel way to understand scientific laws and their necessity. On an existential conception, sciences are practices of research rather than bodies of knowledge extracted from those practices. Heideggerian ontology argues that such practices depend upon a prior understanding of the "being" of entities within the research domain, which governs scientific methodology and conceptualization. This understanding involves both a commitment to the holistic lawfulness of entities in the domain(their behaving "in the same way" no matter what), and a reliable, resilient ability to develop and articulate that understanding in a way that sustains its lawfulness in the face of apparently impossible results. The lawfulness of a scientific domain thus incorporates both the counterfactual invariance of entities within the domain, and the constancy of scientists' comportment toward those entities as lawful, even to the point of abandoning the entire domain if its lawfulness cannot be sustained. This openness to the possibility of conceptual crisis in science is what allows scientific understanding to be truthful, such that the fundamental concepts and methods that provide access to the entities it investigates are also accountable to the entities themselves.

[45]
Schaefer F K, 1953. Exceptionalism in geography: A methodological examination.Annals of the Association of American Geographers, 43(3): 226-249.CiteSeerX - Scientific documents that cite the following paper: Exceptionalism in Geography: A Methodological Examination

DOI

[46]
Smith B, 2003. Ontology. In: Blackwell Guide to the Philosophy of Computing and Information. Oxford: Blackwell, 155-166.

[47]
Stanley L, 2012. Rethinking the definition and role of ontology in political science.Politics, 32(2): 93-99.Ontological reflexivity is consistently posited as an important part of being a political scientist, yet the relevant literature has been criticised for being both complex and confused. In this context, the article has three aims: to clarify the purpose of ontology in the discipline; to highlight how ontological assumptions cannot be separated from other factors; and to show the relevance of ontological reflexivity. While the extant literature implies that such assumptions emerge from philosophical reflection, this article shows how epistemological decisions, mundane interests and political orientation can be just as important. Consequently, the original aims of the literature can be reinstated.

DOI

[48]
Sun J, Pan Y, Tang Met al., 2013. The strategic directions for geography.Acta Geographica Sinica, 68(2): 268-283. (in Chinese)Understanding the Changing Planet: Strategic Directions for the Geographical Sciences (UCP), prepared by the U.S. National Research Council's (NRC) ad hoc Committee on the strategic directions for geographical sciences in the next decade, is an original and agenda-setting document that speaks to transdisciplinary Geographical Sciences in order to get a better understanding of our rapidly changing planet. But for NRC's decision to devote some of the 'precious space' in the report to relatively uncontroversial matters, and UCP was written for the audience which includes people who have little sense of what a geographical 'take' on issues and problems means, as a result the role of technologies and tools is likely to be dominant. The most important contribution of UCP lies in the point of progress of geography in modern times, putting forward the question of Geographical Sciences, and successfully constructing it with the aid of technologies and tools. Another contribution of UCP is the proposed eleven strategic directions for the emerging transdisciplinary field of Geographical Sciences in the next decade. Just a few months later, The Professional Geographer, in a Focus Section, invites five geographers to evaluate UCP briefly, followed by a response from Alexander Murphy on behalf of the NRC Committee, and this focus section initiates a new conversation among geographers about the future of geography. These comments about UCP rediscover and make up the defects of UCP, especially much attention is paid to the methodology of Geographical Sciences. This paper discusses the progress of Geographical Sciences in Chinese Mainland. It illustrates that Chinese Geographical Sciences: (1) are a more complex disciplinary system, well arranged and have a strict category; (2) are balanced in 'discipline' and 'task'; (3) develop some effective methodologies; (4) have showed some far-reaching, concatenate influence. Through reading UCP, the comments and response, and the progress of Chinese Geographical Sciences the paper comes to three conclusions. (1) Geography is just at a crossroad, geographers should take some effective measures to promote it. (2) The balance of 'discipline' and 'task' is the key to the future of Chinese geography. (3) Geographical Sciences should be constructed by disciplinary system, methodology, technologies and tools, and all these three dimensions should be scientifically humanism-based on scientific spirit and directed by humanism.

DOI

[49]
Sun X, 1985. All sciences are ontology and methodology.Social Journal, 18(6): 39-41. (in Chinese)

[50]
Tang M, 2009. The diversification of research approaches in human geography in Chinese Mainland. Geographical Research, 28(4): 865-882. (in Chinese)Beginning with the problems facing the Chinese geographical academia from a review paper on the issues of the progress and retrospect in geography in Chinese mainland,the paper reviews the related research results,and guides the readers to the methodological issues of human geography research.Through the retrospect of the development of human geography approaches and philosophies in the Anglophone world,the author comes to a conclusion that the research paradigm and methodology has been diversified since the 1970s.Through the period from the 1970s to the present,geography was in a state of turmoil.Although Chinese human geographers need not dance to the pipe of the Anglophone counterparts,the diversification of approaches in the Anglophone world can be used as a reference point. Just because of the realization of the limitations of positivist paradigm and reaction,structurism(including Marxism),humanism,feminism,and post-modernism(including poststructurism) appeared and exerted much effect on the research methodologies and paradigms of human geography in Anglophone world.During this course of methodological diversification,geography lost its traditional core but now has a strong periphery. China,as a giant transitional developing country,has a complex geographical pattern of human activities.This complexity is attributed not only to its long history and giant internal inequality,physically and economically,but also to the market-based social and economic reforms.The result is that the postmodern issue parallels the modern problem.This situation gives Chinese human geographers an unprecedented opportunity.The related researches by Chinese human geographers are dominated by empiricism,particularly positivism,and the attention that the researchers paid to the human aspects is not enough.So it is badly needed to diversify the research methodology and approach in order to deepen the researches.The paper discusses the necessity,and gives the countermeasures about the diversification of research approaches in human geography in Chinese Mainland,with the aim to do a little bit to the rational development of human geography in China.

DOI

[51]
Tang M, 2010. The methodological issues of human geography researches in mainland of China.Human Geography, 25(4): 1-6. (in Chinese)Great progress has been made in the research and education of human geography in mainland China.With the rapid development of human geography in the world and the further advance of reform in other spheres in China,some methodological problems in the research of human geography emerged,including the lack or absence of five kinds of academic consciousness(problem consciousness,academic historical consciousness,dialogue consciousness,theoretical consciousness and consciousness of academic norms).Such a situation hinders the development of human geography in China.The reason why there is lack of problem consciousness of human geography researches in mainland China is that there are many papers which are not problem-oriented.The lack is due to the poor postgraduate education,the wrong academic evaluation system and the tradition of the absence of discuss on problems existing in the society and academia.Many Chinese human geography papers cite limited literatures although great progress has been made in the last three decades.This indicates that many human geographers in China lack of the academic historical consciousness and dialogue consciousness,because they just state their own opinions and findings,and pay little attention to the researches of others,and they cannot make a strong academic base of the consulting service.Besides the above substantial academic issues,there are still some formal issues in the academic writings by Chinese human geographers,compared with the national standard or the Anglo-American counterparts.China needs its own 'Chicago Manual of Style'.In order to take part in the world competition of academy,economic development and institution,it is necessary for China to strengthen the consciousness of academic history,dialogue,theory problems and academic norms to make the researches being problem-oriented and theory-oriented,and have enough local bases as well as have original findings.

[52]
Tymoczko T, 1991. Mathematics, science and ontology.Synthese, 88(2): 201-228.

DOI

[53]
Williams M, 1989. Historical geography and the concept of landscape.Journal of Historical Geography, 15(1): 92-104.The landscape has always figured largely in the work of H. C. Darby. It formed an incontestable focus for geographical study, particularly during the early days of his historical-geographical writing. The approaches to landscape employed by Darby are examined, so too are some of the criticisms of his work. Then, both the problem of describing the landscape and the idea of the changing landscape are explored in depth, particularly the themes of the draining of the marshes and the clearing of the forests, against the background of contemporary environmental concerns. The neglect of landscape studies in geography is touched upon as is the current resurgence of landscape oriented studies in many disciplines. Finally, an assessment is attempted of the likely influence and importance of Darby's work on the concept of landscape.

DOI

[54]
Wittgenstein L, 1996. Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus. Beijing: The Commercial Press.

[55]
Worrall J, 1994. The Ontology of Science. Brookfield: Dartmouth.

[56]
Wu K, 2006. On the issues of world view of system theory.Academics in China, 21(5): 99-108. (in Chinese)

[57]
Yang C, 2008. Scientific meaning of Quine’s thought for ontological commitment.Studies in Dialectics of Nature, 24(10): 6-12. (in Chinese)Ontological commitment is Quine's thought for ontology: to be is to be the value of bound variables.The thought had have not only important influence in Philosophy,especially in Philosophy of Science,but also the same meaning in Science.After briefly analyzing the thought of Ontological Commitment in this article,we research the meaning for the thought from many ways in Science.But we don't overall systematically research Quine's scientific thought and basic nation,we only research its meaning in Science from Ontological Commitment.

[58]
Ye C, Cai Y, 2009. Re-evaluating Schaefer and his criticizing on exceptionalism in geography: A case study of the innovation of methodology.Acta Geographica Sinica, 64(9): 1134-1142. (in Chinese)Methodology is a key issue concerning the nature and development direction of geography. Case studies are an important method for methodological research. This paper takes "Exceptionalism in Geography:A Methodological Examination",a classical article in the history of geographical thought,and the debate caused by the article,as a case study. It re-examines and evaluates the background and significance of Schaefer-Hartshorne Debate and makes an in-depth analysis of the nature of the geographical methodology. The case study indicates that methodology is not a set of methods,but the scientism,logic and integration of methods. The basic nature of methodology is the evolutionary dynamics. The approaches to developing methodology in geography can be induced to the traditional type,the innovation type and the adaptation-based type,all of which are essential and equally important for geography. The development of methodology in geography experiences continuously a "negation of negation" dialectic process. Geographers should continue to pursue the methodological research. It is an ungent task for Chinese geographers to hunger for innovation of the methodological research,and a platform should be set up to discuss the methodology. This is the common responsibility of geographers.

DOI

[59]
Ye C, Cai Y, 2010. The geographical methodology between subjectivity and objectivity.Geographical Research, 29(5): 947-958. (in Chinese)

[60]
Yu W, 2002. The resurgence and tendency of research in ontology.Zhejiang Academic Journal, 25(1): 46-52. (in Chinese)

[61]
Yu X, 2012. Ontology. Shanghai: Shanghai People’s Publishing House, 304-305. (in Chinese)

[62]
Zhang H, 1995. Ontology and epistemology: The basic problem of philosophy.The Journal of Humanities, 21(2): 11-15. (in Chinese)

[63]
Zhang N, 2000. The evolution and destiny of Western ontology theory.Philosophical Trends, 22(1): 37-40. (in Chinese)

[64]
Zhang Y, 2005. The truth of existence and existers: The rejuvenation of ontology in contemporary philosophy and the promise of ontology in modern philosophy.Theoretical Investigation, 14(1): 35-39. (in Chinese)

[65]
Zhou M, 2003. Philosophical ontology that pursues the highest rational wisdom.Academic Research, 34(4): 25-28. (in Chinese)

Outlines

/